A Catholic Defense of
Capital Punishment
BY JAMES
JACOBS, AUGUST 17, 2017
Defending
himself against the accusation of capital crimes, Socrates famously asserted
that the main concern should not be the value of a man’s life, but the value of
his life insofar as it is good and just. Socrates crucial point is that justice
is more important than life itself, for an unjust life, as he implies elsewhere
in the Apology, is not worth living. But is there any principle higher than
justice? It would seem so. In the Sermon on the Mount, Christ teaches us to
love our enemies. Any just man will love those who are virtuous; but to love
those who are by nature unlovable simply because they are a child of God
manifests a more profound respect for creation. So, it seems that charity is
more important than justice.
These three
moral imperatives—life, justice, and charity—provocatively clash in the issue
of capital punishment. This conflict is particularly acute for a Christian: as
St. John Paul II argues in Evangelium Vitae, Christian doctrine recognizes the
inviolable dignity of every life, a teaching which would seem to preclude
capital punishment. On the other hand, to say that this dignity invalidates the
claims of justice and overrides the rules of the moral order is self-
contradictory, for human dignity rests upon man’s ability to know and observe
those rules. These competing claims have caused a great deal of uncertainty
within the Catholic Church about the possibility of capital punishment, for the
divergent impulses of justice and charity appear to pull the believer in
opposite directions.
What is
needed is a guide to help us navigate these tumultuous waters. This is the aim
of the new book by Edward Feser and Joseph M. Bessette, By Man Shall His Blood
be Shed: A Catholic Defense of Capital Punishment. Feser, a philosopher, and
Bessette, a lawyer and professor of government, draw deeply from both the
Catholic tradition and contemporary scholarship to show that capital punishment
is not only permissible but even beneficial for society. Their argument, in its
simplest outline, is that “there is a strong moral presumption in favor of
capital punishment for grave crimes such as murder, [and this] presumption can
be overridden only when resorting to capital punishment would fail to serve the
common good as well as a lesser punishment.”
The authors
substantiate these premises with a methodical analysis of the issue from four
perspectives. The first considers capital punishment philosophically, making
incisive arguments based on the natural moral law. This is followed with an
analysis of the theological tradition, showing that Scripture and the constant
teaching of the Church doctors and magisterium affirm the use of capital
punishment. The third section examines the legal and sociological evidence demonstrating
the effectiveness of capital punishment as a penal sanction. Finally, the
authors consider the campaign of the American bishops against capital
punishment in recent decades in order to show that it represents a one-sided
presentation of the relevant data. They conclude that any teaching prohibiting
capital punishment is simply a prudential exhortation, and so is not
doctrinally binding on the laity
The arguments
are offered in a lucid and systematic manner so that they are accessible to
those with no background in philosophy, theology or law. For example, the
opening chapter has an admirably clear introduction to the natural law, and the
second chapter elucidates the relative authority of various theological
sources. They support their argument with copious examples, citing a profusion
of authorities, ancient and modern. Conversely, they engage a wide range of
objections to their position with great dialectical subtlety. Though there is a
certain amount of repetition, this works to impress the logic of their position
on the reader. And, although this clearly is a defense of the legitimacy of
capital punishment, the authors are forthright that this establishes only that
it is allowable, not that it is required. To put it another way, since “there
are no good arguments for abolishing capital punishment,” the question of
whether to apply it must be made in light of the concrete circumstances of each
case. The authors take Cardinal Ratzinger’s opinion as their touchstone: “There
may be legitimate diversity of opinion even among Catholics about … applying
the death penalty.”
Because
opposition to capital punishment is often framed in emotional terms, the
authors begin their assessment by outlining the logical reasons behind the
Church’s teaching as articulated by natural law ethics. The natural law asserts
there is an objective order of justice that must be respected if human beings
are to flourish. Punishment, then, exists for the sake of restoring that
natural order of justice if it has been broken by some crime. Punishment is
therefore a moral requirement, and not merely a utilitarian remedy to protect
society. This sort of justice, which must not be confused with an amoral desire
for vengeance based on hatred, is known as retributive justice. Importantly, if
retribution is to restore the order of justice, the punishment needs to be
proportionate to the offense. This sense of proportional retribution is the
primary characteristic of just punishment: the offender must pay for his crime.
In addition to retribution, there are two additional purposes for punishment:
rehabilitation of the offender and deterrence of similar offenses.
While the
propriety of capital punishment will be evaluated in terms of all these ends,
it is retribution that is the primary criterion in determining whether it is a
just punishment. The crucial premise, then, is that “some crimes are so grave
that no punishment less than death would be proportionate in its severity.” The
rationale is made clear by assuming that the most heinous crime, mass murder or
genocide, does not merit death. If absolutely nothing merited death, then the
whole idea of proportionality would be destroyed. That, in turn, would subvert
the notion of retributive justice itself, for any punishment might be given for
any crime. Thus, the authors conclude “the legitimacy of punishment in general
and the legitimacy in principle of capital punishment in particular stand or
fall together.” Furthermore, the authors argue, because capital punishment also
accomplishes the ends of rehabilitation and deterrence, there is no reason to
oppose its use in a just society.
Feser and
Bessette next consider the Church’s position as articulated in Scripture and
Tradition. The evidence they present from the Bible, Church Fathers, popes, and
councils demonstrates that the Church has always believed capital punishment to
be permissible when justly implemented. The title of the book is taken from
Genesis 9:6, which justifies capital punishment as the only reasonable reaction
to murder because man is made in God’s image. The New Testament, particularly
the Sermon on the Mount, might seem more problematic, but the authors show that
these counsels are intended to guide the individual Christian, who is called to
a life of charity, and not the state, which is instituted to defend justice in
society. Developing these Scriptural principles, the theological Tradition
takes it for granted that capital punishment is an acceptable form of
discipline. The unanimous evidence dating from the third century indicates that
this is a definitive teaching of the Church that cannot be changed even by
popes.
Many assume,
though, that this position was challenged by John Paul II in Evangelium Vitae
and the Catechism. These documents, while accepting the traditional teaching of
the Church, insist that a modern state has the capacity to adequately punish
the offender and protect society without shedding blood, and so Christians
should support non-lethal punishments. The authors respond that this teaching
cannot be understood to be a departure from the tradition; rather, it should be
seen as a prudential judgment, an application of a moral principle about which
there can be diversity of opinion.
The third
chapter brings forth a great deal of empirical data from the courts concerning
the use of capital punishment to demonstrate that it is both proportionate to
the offense and rehabilitative of the offender. Since many question whether
execution can ever be proportionate, the analysis begins with a litany of
horrific accounts of the forty-three people executed in 2012; this is not easy
reading, but it illustrates the depravity of those who are sentenced to death.
In light of these details, the public can have confidence in the justice of
their society only if these murderers suffer truly proportional retribution,
that is, death. Moreover, the personal stories of those who were sentenced show
that many were led to contrition, and even conversion, as a result of facing
execution.
The final
chapter examines how since 1974 the American Bishops have tended to condemn
capital punishment as intrinsically opposed to Catholic teaching, making it
equivalent to abortion and euthanasia. The bishops cite three arguments in
defense of this position: it fails to achieve the goals of punishment; it is
inconsistent with Gospel values; and, it is applied in a discriminatory
fashion. The authors reply by showing that each of these arguments is
indefensible when considered in light of the constant Tradition of the Church
and contemporary studies. They also offer an examination of capital punishment
as a deterrent, citing empirical data showing that it inculcates a repugnance
to crime in general.
The failure
of the bishops’ arguments leads the authors to conclude that, given the
singular importance of retributive justice, the culture of life is in fact
better served when capital punishment is employed, for only then will the
dignity of innocent life be fully defended.
This
conclusion underscores the fact that there are actually two arguments being
made in the book. The first is that the Church’s position on capital punishment
has always been that it is not intrinsically evil, but it is rather a matter of
prudential decision about which there can be valid disagreement. This argument
is completely convincing, given the abundance of evidence from philosophy,
Scripture, and Tradition.
There is a
second argument, however, that is rarely explicitly thematized, which runs
along with the first. This is a positive commendation of capital punishment as
being good, for the authors claim that without it the very idea of proportional
punishment and the dignity of human life would be lost. This argument not only
opposes the abolition of capital punishment, but advocates “applying it with
some frequency.”
This
conclusion should engender continued debate about capital punishment. While it
is clear that employing capital punishment is permissible and just, how often
to employ it involves prudential analysis by those who are best informed of the
case. Prudence aims for not only what is permissible, but what is best. This
seems to be the significance of John Paul’s exhortation, and it is a point
worthy of serious consideration. However, to enact that exhortation is
increasingly difficult. While we are called to observe the precepts of both
justice and charity, the real problem about our current debate is the fact
that, as the authors repeatedly note, our society has utterly lost its sense of
justice.
[PHOTO SOURCE: http://victimsfamiliesforthedeathpenalty.blogspot.com.au/2016/01/saint-thomas-aquinas-on-death-penalty.html] |
Without a
sense of justice, we cannot recognize the need for proportionate retribution;
worse, this then obscures how charity is a perfection of natural justice by
isolating the redemptive from the creative order. Lacking the objective
reference of justice, opinions on capital punishment devolve to emotivism:
support for it evinces anger, while opposition evinces sentimentality. To kill
out of anger is clearly wrong. However, far worse is selectively opposing
capital punishment without embracing the totality of the justice and the
Gospel, for that can only be a sentimentality that disrespects the dignity of
man and God alike. But, I might suggest in accord with Feser and Bessete, we
can begin to reclaim the liberating power of charity by first respecting the
obligations of justice.
___________________________
James Jacobs
is Professor of Philosophy and Assistant Academic Dean at Notre Dame Seminary
in New Orleans, LA. His major area of research is Thomistic natural law theory,
and more generally the need for a philosophical realism as a response to modern
nominalism and skepticism. Professor Jacobs earned his doctorate in philosophy
from Fordham University.
INTERNET SOURCE: http://www.crisismagazine.com/2017/catholic-church-capital-punishment
& https://catholiccitizens.org/views/73332/catholic-defense-capital-punishment/
No comments:
Post a Comment