NOTICE: The following article is
written by the author itself and not by us, we are not trying to violate their
copyright. We will give some information on them. Unit 1012 will post a quote
or article from a Christian in favor of capital punishment every fortnight. We
chose this as the Christian Article for the Death Penalty of the fortnight because
Clergyman, Alexander Campbell passed away on this date, March 4, 1866. In
loving memory of him, we will post his article as the Christian Article for the
death penalty.
PAGE TITLE: http://www.mun.ca/rels/restmov/
ARTICLE
TITLE: IS
CAPITAL PUNISHMENT SANCTIONED BY DIVINE AUTHORITY?
DATE: Before 1866
AUTHOR: Alexander Campbell
AUTHOR
INFORMATION: Alexander Campbell (12 September 1788 – 4 March
1866) was an early leader in the Second Great Awakening of the religious
movement that has been referred to as the Restoration Movement, or
Stone-Campbell Movement. The Campbell wing of the movement was said to begin
with his father Thomas Campbell's publication in 1809 in Washington County,
Pennsylvania, of The Declaration and Address of the Christian Association of
Washington. In 1832 the group of reformers led by the Campbells merged with a
similar group that began in Kentucky under the leadership of Barton W. Stone.
Several American church groups trace their history to the Campbells'
leadership, including the Churches of Christ, the Independent Christian
Churches/Churches of Christ, Evangelical Christian Church in Canada, and the
Christian Church (Disciples of Christ). Alexander Campbell is also the founder
of Bethany College in Bethany, West Virginia.
URL: http://www.mun.ca/rels/restmov/texts/acampbell/capital.html
(Dead Link)
Alexander Campbell
|
ESSAY
IS CAPITAL PUNISHMENT SANCTIONED BY DIVINE AUTHORITY?
IS CAPITAL PUNISHMENT SANCTIONED BY DIVINE AUTHORITY?
The true
philosophy of man, even amongst philosophers themselves, is yet a desideratum.
We are all agreed that neither the Egyptians nor the Chaldeans, neither the
Medes nor the Persians, neither the Greeks nor the Romans, had attained to the
true science of man. They had their astrologers, soothsayers and magicians.
They had their sages, philosophers and poets as they had their great generals,
heroes and conquerors. They had their sciences and arts, both useful and
ornamental; but they had not the knowledge of themselves; they had not the
Bible. Hence their proper origin, relations, obligations and destiny, were to
them alike unknown and unknowable. The profound Socrates, the learned and acute
Aristotle, the splendid and erudite Plato, the still more enlightened and
eloquent Cicero, were as profoundly ignorant of their own moral constitution
and moral relations to the great unknown and eternal God, as they were of the
grand discoveries and inventions of the present century.
We may,
indeed, have as exaggerated views of our own attainments in this our "age
of reason", "march of mind", and brilliant advances into the
mysteries of nature, as they had of themselves and their attainments.
Posterity, too, may look back upon our age as we are wont to contemplate ages
long since passed away, and wish, as "duteous sons, their fathers had been
more wise." Certain it is, that we are not satisfied with ourselves, and
that a spirit of inquiry, revolution and change is now abroad in the land,
which no man can limit or restrain.
We live
in the midst of a great moral revolution. Opinions held sacred by our fathers,
usages consecrated by the devotion of ages, institutions venerated by the most
venerable of mankind are now subjected to the same cold, rigid analysis, and
made to pass through the same unsparing ordeal, to which the most antiquated
errors and the most baseless hypotheses of the most reckless innovators are now
so /312/ unmercifully doomed. Few, indeed, of the most popular theories of the
Pagan schools on the great subject of man's social and moral relations, have,
when cast into this fiery furnace, like Shadrach, Meshach and Abed-nego, came
out unscathed.
Times of
revolution are, however, more or less, dangerous times. For, as in the
tumultuous rage of passions long pent up, and in the fitful frenzy of an
inflamed multitude long down- trodden, the innocent with the guilty are
sometimes immolated on the same altar, reared to the presiding genius of
revolt; so truths rightfully enthroned in the judgement of the intelligent, and
deeply cherished in the hearts of the faithful, are in times of great
excitement, and in the reign of scepticism, repudiated as reprobate silver, and
sacrificed at the shrine of a licentious and indiscriminating spirit of
innovation.
Ours,
however, is an age of invention, rather than of discovery: the arts, more than
the sciences are cultivated and improved. The invention of printing, the discovery
of America, and the Protestant reformation, have imparted to the human mind an
impulse so vigorous and so enduring, that neither time nor space seem able to
impair it. Stimulated by former conquests over error, and the new discoveries
since made, the human mind seems intent on carrying on war against false
assumptions and unwarranted conclusions--as if determined to advance from
victory to victory over every species of error and delusion: so that we may not
unreasonably anticipate a day when the last error shall be exploded, and the
last baseless assumption shall be entombed in the same unfathomable abyss with
the vortices of Descartes, or in the nethermost hollow sphere of the
speculative and hypothetical, though ingenious, Captain Symmes.
But there
are many things already established. The human mind is not wholly at sea
without pilot or compass. The mariner's compass has been invented. And many
truths are immovably fixed and certain in every well-cultivated and intelligent
mind.
Physical
nature is, indeed, still open to investigation in some of her most interesting
and sublime departments. Astronomy is yet in progress of development. Geology
is a new science, still incomplete and imperfect. The physical constitution of
man has yet numerous mysteries that sealed from the most discriminating eye.
Not only several of its most sublime and delicate tissues are unexplored, but
the design as well as the peculiar structure of some of its organs are
unappreciated and unknown. The human head has only recently been explored and
developed by the mighty genius and indefatigable of a Gall and Spurzheim. That
men have souls as well as bodies, and spirits as /313/ souls, seems likely soon
to be satisfactorily proved, not by metaphysical reasoning, but by ocular and
sensible demonstrations. Nor is the day far distant when it is presumed that
all parties will agree that, as God has made the world, he should govern it.
There
are, indeed, two sciences, and but two, wholly unsusceptible of improvement.
These, the author of the universe, by a patent which no man can invade but at
the peril of his eternal destiny, has both wisely and kindly reserved to
himself. I need not say that these are the sciences of religion and morality.
No angelic being, unable to survey the universe in its infinite and eternal
dimensions, nor man, in all his mysterious and sublime organization and
capacities, could possibly project or develop these. They are the sciences,
which by an insuperable and stern necessity, are not merely superhuman, but
supernatural and divine. There is a world above us and a world within us for
which no man or angel could legislate. There is a moral code beyond the
capacity and supervision of man-extending, too, in its requisition into a
kingdom over which no human tribunal can find any jurisdiction, and which is
necessary to moral government as oxygen to combustion, or caloric to human
life. There is an empire in the human heart over which no man or angel can
preside, and a throne in the midst of it on which no king can sit but the King
of Eternity. For this reason alone, which as good as a thousand, and to which
the addition of a thousand could give no weight, religion and morals are
sciences wholly supernatural and divine.
Civil
government is itself a divine appendix to the volumes of religion and morality.
Though neither Caesar nor Napoleon, Nicholas nor Victoria, were, "BY THE
GRACE OF GOD," king, emperor or queen; still the civil throne, the civil
magistrate, and, therefore, civil government, are, BY THE GRACE OF GOD,
bestowed upon the world. Neither the church nor the world could exist without
it. God himself has, therefore, benevolently ordained magistrates and judges.
Men may call them kings, emperors or presidents, (for much of politics, like
much of speculative theology, is but a mere logomachy--a war of ill-assorted
words,) but they are God's ministers, executors of his will and of his
vengeance, ordained to wait upon him and to execute his mandates. They are sort
of viceroys--vicegerents under a law to God, and to govern according to his
revealed will. The bible is of right, and it ought to be, just as much a law to
kings and governors and presidents, as it is to masters and servants, to
husbands and wives, to parents and children. Those magistrates, therefore, who
will not be governed and /314/ guided by it in the faithful execution of God's
laws, God himself, in his own proper person, will judge and punish.
Since the
days of Plato, men have conceived republics. They have invented new orders of
society, new theories of socialism, and new names for things. But these are
mere demonstrations of human weakness and of human scepticism. The bible has
sanctioned republics and commonwealths and kingdoms without affixing any
peculiar name to them. It prescribes no form of human government, because no
one form of government would suit all the countries, climes and people of the
earth. But the bible, in the name and by the authority of its Author, demands
all persons in authority that they protect the innocent, and that they punish
the guilty, and that they dispense justice to all. It also demands of the
governed that they submit to "THE POWERS THAT BE," however
denominated, as an ordinance of God; not through the fear of the sword, but for
the sake of conscience. It inhibits them also from treason, insubordination and
rebellion.
In the
freedom of debate, and in harmony with that sprit of innovation of which we
have just spoken, a question has been mooted, and is now before the American
public, a matter of very grave discussion. A question, too, than which, in my
humble judgement, no one pertaining to this life is worthy of a more profound
deliberation, nor whose decision is fraught with more fearful and important
results, affecting the whole community, involving the foundation of civil
government, all the fixtures of society, the extent of all earthly sovereignty,
and all the principles of international law, commerce and responsibility. That
question is propounded in the solemn interrogatory, IS CAPITAL PUNISHMENT
SANCTIONED BY A DIVINE AUTHORITY? or, in other words, HAS MAN THE RIGHT TO TAKE
AWAY THE LIFE OF MAN ON ANY ACCOUNT WHATSOEVER?
If he
have not a divine right I frankly admit that he has no human right--no warrant
or authority derived from man--that will authorize such a solemn and fearful
act. Though we should not, in the first instance, take into account the
consequences of any decision, as having direct authority in influencing our
reasonings upon the question, still it is important that we have some respect
for them as arguments and incentives to a calm discreet and patient
investigation of the premises from which are to be adduced conclusions so
deeply involving the interests of the world.
And what,
let me inquire, would be the consequences should it be decided that no man has
no right to take away the life of man on any account whatsoever? Is it not the
right to inflict upon him any penal /315/ pain whatever involved in this
question? A single stripe may kill; nay, a single stripe inflicted by an
officer of justice, and that no very violent one, has sometimes killed. A man
has no right to punish at all in any way, if he may not in that punishment
lawfully take away the life of him that is subjected to it. He has not even the
right to imprison or confine a person in jail, workhouse or penitentiary, if he
have not, in any case whatever, the right to kill. How many die in jails,
workhouses and penitentiaries, from causes to which they would not have been
exposed but in those places of punishment!
But,
further, if a man has not the right to kill, nations have no right to go to war
in any case, or for any purpose whatever. We argue that whatever power a
Government has is first found in the people; that men can not innocently or
rightfully do that conventionally, or in states, which they can not do in their
individual capacities. True, when a government is organized, the citizens or
subjects of it cannot use or exercise the powers to legislate, to judge, to
punish, which, by the social compact, they have, for wise purposes, surrendered
or transferred to the Government. Still, the fundamental fact must not be lost
sight of- -that NATIONS HAVE THE RIGHT TO DO THOSE THINGS ONLY WHICH EVERY
INDIVIDUAL MAN HAD A RIGHT TO DO ANTERIOR TO THE NATIONAL FORM OF SOCIETY. If,
then, man had not originally a right to kill him who killed his brother,
society never could, but from a special law of the creator, have such a right.
And such, we may hereafter show, was originally the divine law. The natural
reason of man, or a divine law, enacted that the blood of the murdered should
be avenged by the blood of the murderer, and that the brother of the murdered
was pre-eminently the person to whom belonged the right of avenging his blood.
Wars are
either defensive or aggressive. But, in either point of view they are
originated and conducted on the assumption that man has a right, for just
cause, to take away the life of a man. For it needs no argument to convince
anyone, however obtuse, that man cannot rightfully kill a thousand or a million
of persons, if he cannot lawfully kill one! I wonder not, then, that peace-men
are generally, if not universally, in favour of the total abolition of capital
punishment.
What an
immense train of consequences hand upon the final and correct decision of this
question! Wars would, from an insuperable necessity, cease. We should then,
indeed, "beat our swords into ploughshares and our spears into
pruning-hooks." We could hang the war-trumpet in the halls of peace, and
study war no more. Cannon, military establishments, standing armies, mighty
navies, ex- /316/ tensive arsenals, and all the other munitions of war, would
no longer be the ULTIMA RATIO REGUM. No longer would governments rely upon the
arm of flesh for self-defense or for redress of wrongs. What millions of gold
would be saved, and what oceans of blood would be prevented!
It is
true, however, that wars might cease and universal peace spread its halcyon
wings over the earth, and still the murderer be rightfully, and by the supreme
authority of the state, put to death. There is no incompatibility whatever in
the argument of settling national controversies by another way than by war. We
may settle them as we pacifically settle individual and corporate
misunderstandings, and still argue against the abolition of capital punishment.
But our argument is, that there would be an end of all wars, offensive and
defensive, in the national mind, if men have no right to kill those who have
killed their neighbours. Certainly, no one would place himself in the absurd attitude
of defending wars for territory--for mere depredations on trade and
commerce--in defense of chartered rights or violated treaties, if it can be
shown that we ought not to wage war against the most savage tribes and
barbarous nations for having butchered our wives and children.
Again,
nations may not rightfully go to war--if man cannot, in any case, lawfully take
away the life of a man, in how dishonorable an attitude stand the patriots of
all Christian lands--the Hampdens, the La Fayettes, the Washingtons! and where
stand the men of faith, the men of sacred fame--the Joshuas, the Samsons, the
Baraks, the Gideons, the Davids?
And what
shall we say of the morality of those who do honor to their memory? Of those
who are always approbating, applauding and eulogizing our own Revolutionary
heros and those who distinguished themselves in the Indian wars--in wars
against untutored savages, desirous to retain and defend their patrimonial
inheritance from European invasion and aggression--of those, a very numerous
host of patriotic contemporaries, who have no civil honors to bestow, no civic
wreath prepared, but to adorn the brows of military chieftain whose garments
have been rolled in the blood of vanquished enemies--and especially those who
desire new wars for manufacturing new generals and new heros, the idols of a
nation's, to fill the empty niches in the temple of our heroic fancies!
Such are
a few of the consequences that must follow the decision of the question before
us in the negative. Still, as before said, we only use these arguments for a
calm, dispassionate and thorough investi- /317/ gation of the subject. It must
be tried by some law and before some tribunal having supreme authority in the
case. But what shall be that law, and where shall that tribunal be found? Is it
not the law of phrenology--of expediency- -of tradition--of our common
statute-books--of even public opinion. None of these have legitimate
jurisdiction over a question that has so much of the temporal and eternal
fortunes of human kind at stake.
We may,
indeed, listen, either for instruction or amusement, to the pleasing fancies of
poets--to the visions of enthusiastic philanthropists--to the decisions of
various sects of philosophers, or to the codes and enactments of olden times and
of fallen empires; but from their speculations or their decisions we can derive
neither argument nor authority.
Some of
the most dogmatical of the new schools of philosophy assume that the sole end
of punishment is the reformation of the offender; that the murderer must be
send to a school of repentance and be better educated, and, when properly
instructed and honorably graduated, he shall have his passport into the
confidence of society, and be permitted to develop himself in the midst of more
favorable circumstances. Such is one of the more popular substitutes for
capital punishment. Plato's favorite dogmas--that man was made for philosophy,
and not philosophy for man--that perfect civil code would make a notion
virtuous--and that offenders could be reformed by wise and benevolent
exhortations--are not more whimsical and ridiculous than the theories of such
abolitionists of capital punishment. They are, indeed, but an ingenious preface
to the Elysian hell of some Universalian philanthropists, who imagine that
place of punishment to be but a portico to heaven--a sort of purgatorial
ante-chamber, in which men are to be purified by gentle flames for an induction
to the inner most sanctuary of the universe.
We agree
with those who affirm that punishments ought, in all cases, to be enacted and
enforced with a special regard to the reformation of transgressors; but we can
not say with an EXCLUSIVE regard. Empathetic and special, but not EXCLUSIVE,
regard, should be shown to the reformation of the criminal. There must also be
a special and a supreme regard to the safety of the state, and the protection
of the innocent and unoffending. The laws of every civilized community should
unite as far as possible the reformation of the offender with the safety of the
state.
But how
these two may best be secured, is a matter yet not agreed. A sentence of
perpetual imprisonment is no guarantee of protection /318/ or safety to the
state. The sentence, in the first place, may not be executed. It seldom is, in
the case of persons holding high places in society. Governors sometimes
reprieve. political demagogues, too, will not very conscientiously demur at the
offer of many suffrages for a gubernatorial chair, on a private understanding
that certain persons of influential connections sentenced to perpetual
imprisonment shall on their election be pardoned. But, further, it is no
guarantee that the monster who has been guilty of one murder may not murder his
attendants or fellow-prisoners in hope of escape or that he may not fire his
prison or in some way elope. He may be confined for life, and yet may again
perpetuate the same foul crime. Are there not numerous instances of this kind
on record? And has not the professedly reformed and pardoned criminal at times
been guilty of a second, and sometimes of a theirs, murder? Such instances have
been known in our own country and in our own memory. A sentence of perpetual
confinement is not an adequate security against a murderer, in any view that
can be taken of it Society demands a higher pledge of safety--a more
satisfactory guarantee. It demands the life of a murderer.
And
strange as it might seem, we affirm the conviction that the certainty of death,
is upon all premises, the most efficient means of reformation. When--I do not
say the UNFORTUNATE, (a name too full of sophistry, though unfortunate he may
be,) but--the MALIGNANT AND WICKED MURDERER has been tried, convicted and
sentenced to die after the lapse of so many days or weeks, when all hope of
pardon is forever gone, then evangelical instruction is incomparably more
likely to effect a change than are the chances of a long or short life within
the walls of a penitentiary. It is, therefore, I must think, more rational and
humane, whether we consider the safety of the state or the happiness of the
individual, to insist that the sentence of death be promptly and firmly
executed.
So we
reason against the assumptions of those who would abolish capital punishment,
on the ground that all punishment should be for the salvation of the transgressor,
and that his imprisonment for life, or till evident reformation, is an ample
pledge for the safety and security of the state.
They
reason as illogically against capital punishment who assume that imprisonment
for life is a greater punishment than death. Satan, more than three thousand
years ago, reasoned more logically than they. He then argued in the face of
high authority, on the trial of a very distinguished person, that a man would
give the world for his life. /319/ "Skin for skin, all that a man
hath," said the devil, "will he give for his life."
I am
reminded of one of the fables of Aesop in the only speech I ever read in favor
of capital punishment, so far as my memory bears witness. The writer, in
disproof of the assumption that imprisonment for life is a greater punishment
than death, adduces the following fable:--"Aesop has finely satirized the
prevalent disposition to complain of life as a burden when we are oppressed by
the ills to which humanity is heir. We are all familiar with the fable of the
poor man who was groaning under the weight of the fagots which he was carrying
to his home. Weary and exhausted, he threw his load from his shoulders, sat
down by the wayside, and loudly invoked Death to come an relieve him from his
misery. Instantly the greedy tyrant stood before him, and, with an uplifted
dart, inquired, `what wouldst thou have with me?' `Good Death,' exclaimed the
poor man, in terrified amazement, `I want thee to help me get this bundle of
sticks upon my back.' The fable needs no interpreter. It's moral is
obvious." Were imprisonment for life a severer punishment than death, it
would not be lawful to exact it, so far as the divine law indicates what is
just and equal. Neither the LEX TALIONIS, nor the bible, nor right reason, so
far as I can judge, would authorize any punishment severer than death.
But we
can very sincerely sympathize with many good men in their aversion to capital
punishment for any other crime than murder. Indeed, much of the excitement and
indignation against capital punishment arises from two sources:--the many
crimes that have been judged worthy of death; and the fact that innocent
sometimes suffer while the guilty escape. In noticing the various topics from
which men reason against the justice of demanding life for life, our design is
to show how doubtful and inconclusive all mere human reasonings and statutes on
this on this subject must be, rather than to enter into a full investigation of
all that may be alleged from these sources of reason and argumentation.
We
cheerfully admit that our criminal code is not in unison with the spirit of
that age, nor with the presiding genius of European and American civilization.
Christian justice, humanity and mercy have, indeed, in some countries, and in
none more than in our own, greatly modified and improved political law and
political justice./320/
Public
opinion has for more than a century been vacillating between two extreme
systems of punishment-- one of which punishes more than a hundred varieties of
offense with death, while the other inflicts death on no transgressor for any
crime whatever. During the reign of sanguinary law in England, as Blackstone
very correctly observes, "it is a melancholy truth, that among the variety
of actions which men are daily liable to commit, no less than a hundred and
sixty have been declared, by act of Parliament, to be felonies without benefit
of clergy; or, in other words, to be worthy of instant death. So dreadful a
list," adds the learned jurist, "instead of diminishing, increases
the number of offenders."
Such a
criminal code was, indeed, very likely to lead to another extreme. It has,
therefore, been yielding in severity to the more humane genius of modern
civilization. The human mind, ocean like, has its ebbings and flowings, its
high tides and its low tides, on all exciting subjects. Time was when an
Englishman forfeited his life for a very paltry theft--for the mere purloining
of twelvepence sterling. That there ought to be a correspondence between
offenses and their punishment, is an oracle of reason and justice, so obvious
to all, that it may be regarded in the light of a primary truth--a sort of
self-evident proposition, that needs only to be stated to any person of
reflection to secure his immediate assent.
We
advocate a discriminating tariff of penalties and punishments, not for the sake
of revenue alone, but for the sake of protecting innocence and virtue. We have
no faith either in the justice of expediency of a horizontal tariff, awarding
one and the same punishment to each and to every one of a hundred crimes. we
would not hang one man for stealing a shilling, and inflict the same punishment
for treason, sacrilege, rape or murder. We believe in the scriptural phrases,
"worthy of stripes," "worthy of a sorer punishment," and
"worthy of death." These forms of speech occur in both Testaments,
but more frequently in the New than in the Old. They are phrases from which a
sound and irrefutable argument in support of capital punishment may be deduced,
and which no one opposed to it will dare on any occasion to employ.
With the
profound Montesquieu, I argue that "the severity of laws prevents their
execution; and, therefore, whenever punishment transcends reasonable limits,
the public will not unfrequently prefer impunity to inhumanity or to excessive
punishment." Nay, with a greater than Montesquieu, I believe that an eye
should not be taken for a tooth, nor a whole years imprisonment for man's whole
life. /321/ The penal code of every community should be an index of its moral
sense and moral character. It ought to be regarded as a licensed exposition of
its views upon the comparative criminality and malignity of every action
affecting the life, the liberty, the character or the prosperity of its
citizens,--a polished mirror from which may be reflected upon its own citizens
and upon the world at large a nations intelligence, moral taste and moral
excellency. Should it affix the same punishment to various and numerous
offenses, irrespective of their grade in criminality, it will confound and
bewilder the moral perceptions of the people, and exhibit to the world a very
fallacious test of the comparative atrocity and malignity of human actions.
It may,
indeed, be assumed that all sins are equally violations of the law of God--equally
dishonorable to his majesty-- equally obnoxious to his displeasure--and,
therefore, equally to be punished. But be this view abstractly right or wrong,
it is alien to our subject; for it is only with sin as it RESPECTS MAN in its
injurious tendency that human legislation and human punishment have to do. The
lord has reserved to himself the right to punish sin as committed against
himself, and has delegated man the authority to punish sin only in so far as it
is fraught with evils to the human race. In this view alone are sins to be
estimated more or less atrocious, and more or less severely to be punished. The
doctrines of sound reason , as well as that of revelation, is, "that every
transgression and disobedience of the divine law should receive a just and
adequate recompense of reward."
From such
considerations and reasonings such as these, we could advocate a scale of
punishments in harmony with the most correct views of the criminality and
wickedness of human actions, rising up to capital punishments only in the case
of wilful and deliberate murder, not to be extenuated in any case by passion,
intemperance, or any temptation whatsoever. To obviate the exception not
unfrequently taken to capital punishment on the ground that sometimes the
innocent may suffer while the guilty escape, might there not be such legal
provisions as would prevent the possibility of any one being convicted without
such strength of testimony and proof of guilt as would not leave the shadow of
a doubt? We doubt not the practicability of such a provision. Thus we reason
with those who reason from their conceptions of the congruity, expediency and
rational propriety of human theories and codes as respects penal statutes in
general, and capital punishment in particular. Should we, then, claim no more
authority for our reasonings than those who differ from us claim for theirs,
(though, of course, /322/ we suppose we have the stronger and the better
reasons,) we have gained this point, that, in demurring to our conclusions, we
must both appeal to a higher court, and await the decision of the Supreme
Law-giver and Judge of the universe. This is all we have sought in these
preliminary views and reasonings; and certainly it will be conceded to us by
those who may dissent from the positions we have already assumed.
In this
present erratic world there are two ultra schools of philosophy:--the one takes
nothing, the other takes almost every thing, on credit. With the one, their
fathers are wiser than their sons; with the other, the sons are wiser than
their fathers. The antiquity of an opinion is a passport to the favor of one;
the novelty of an opinion is secures for it a favorable introduction to the
confidence of the other. The tendency of the one school is to a blind devotion;
that of the other to an absolute scepticism. we will not abide by the decision
of either school. We prefer to carry this question up to a higher court--to a
Judge who perfectly comprehends the whole constitution of man as an animal,
intellectual and moral being--by whom the fundamental laws of the moral
universe, and man in all his mysterious and sublime relations to that universe,
are contemplated--not in the dim light of time, but in the clear and bright
effulgence of a glorious and awful eternity. We, therefore, appeal from all
human reasonings and from all human codes to the infallible decisions of that
court as registered in the faithful records of the Old and New Testaments. The
question before us is, WHAT PUNISHMENT DOES THE SUPREME LAWGIVER AND JUDGE
AWARD TO THE MURDERER? This is a mere question of fact, and not of a
philosophical theory. We must, then, decide it by testimony. We shall,
therefore, make a direct appeal to the Divine Record, and endeavour to find an
answer for it from an induction of the cases and statutes therein recorded; or,
at least, so many of them as will satisfactorily indicate the Divine will on
the subject.
The first
case in the annals of time brought before this court was that of Cain, indicted
for the murder of his brother Abel. Abel's blood, thus shed, in the judgement
of God called for vengeance on him that shed it. His words are, "The voice
of thy brothers blood crieth unto me from the ground." He immediately
added, "Thou art cursed from the earth," dooming him to become
"a fugitive and a vagabond."
This
excommunication beyond the pale of the Divine protection, Cain understood to be
a licence given to any person to kill him. His language clearly indicates
this:--"It shall come to pass," said he, /323/ "that every one
who findth me shall kill me." A single question on this case, it seems,
might decide the matter: viz. Was this the voice of reason, the voice of
conscience, or the voice of God? Rather, was it not the voice of them all? If
so, then, is not the crime of murder on its first appearance, judged worthy of
death?
Does
anyone doubt it? Let him place the matter before his own mind in the form of a
trilemma. Either Cain's own natural reason and conscience, or an antecedent
law, or the sentence God pronounced upon him, decreed his death for that crime.
Can anyone assign for any other reason than someone of these three as extorting
from Cain the declaration that "every one who findeth me will kill
me"? The whole three may, indeed, have conspired to produce the
conviction; but certainly someone of them did; and this is enough to prove
that, in the sight of God, his crime was worthy of death: for none of the three
could exist without a revelation from God. such was the decision of the first
case. God, indeed, for reasons growing out the condition of the world at that
period, was pleased to reprieve him for the time being, and gave him a pledge
that no one should kill him.
Some may
ask, Why did not God himself immediately kill Cain, seeing that his brother's
blood called for vengeance? To which several answers may be given; such
as--God, who knows the hearts of all men, and whose prerogative it is to show
mercy, may have known that Cain did not intent to kill his brother but only to
humble him; or he may have judged it expedient to give proof of his mercy in
the exercise of his sovereignty in the beginning of the world, waiting till
further developments of the violence of human passion would justify him before
the universe of inflicting adequate penalties upon transgressors; and also in demonstration
of another truth, viz. that a government all mercy would not promote the safety
or happiness of man; for this experiment resulted in the earth's being so
filled with violence that God was finally constrained to punish the
antediluvins by one common death inflicted by his own hand. This was capital
punishment in the superlative degree.
What
numerous and various acts of violence characterized the antediluvian world we
were not informed. What laws were promulged by Divine authority we are not told.
But the silence of antiquity is no proof that such laws were not enacted. For,
although we have no published code of antediluvian laws, we have allusions to
existing institutions which could not have been introduced without laws. A
priesthood, alters, victims and sacrifices could not have existed without
positive law. The distribution of animals into clean and unclean with /324/
regard not to food, but to sacrifice, presupposes very clear and positive
enactments. Neither Abel, nor Seth, nor Enoch, could have pleased God, or
walked with God, without law. The light of nature could not have originated
alters, victims and priests. Indeed, the fact that the earth as filled with
violence, it is no inconsiderable argument that the will of God had been
revealed; for where no law is, there is no transgression.
But,
besides what is affirmed of vengeance in the case of Cain, we have, so late as
the time of his great-great grandson, Lamech, another very direct reference to
the punishment of murder. Lamach, of the family of Cain, was the first
polygamists known to history. His wives, Adah and Zillah, being apprehensive of
the vengeance threatened, called forth from him the oldest poem in the world.
It may be translated as follows:--
"Adah
and Zillah, hear my voice;
Wives of Lamech, hearken to my speech;--
for I have slain a man for wounding me,
A young man for having beaten me.
If Cain be avenged sevenfold,
Surely Lamach seventy-and-seven."
Wives of Lamech, hearken to my speech;--
for I have slain a man for wounding me,
A young man for having beaten me.
If Cain be avenged sevenfold,
Surely Lamach seventy-and-seven."
This,
being written in hemistichs in the original, is generally, by the learned,
regarded as the oldest poetry in the literature of the world. There is, to my
mind, but one ambiguity in the passage. It respects the punctuation of the
third line. It may be read interrogatively or indicatively:--either,
"I
have slain a man for wounding me,"
or,
"Have
I slain a man for wounding me, A young man for having bruised me?"
Read
indicatively, it intimates that Lamech killed a man in self-defence. Read
interrogatively, it denies that he killed any person. In either case, he
rebukes the evil forebodings of his wives; for if any one killed him, not being
guilty of murder, sevenfold vengeance would be inflicted upon him more than on
Cain,- than which we know of nothing more terrible. On the above version I may
say I have the Jewish Targums, Adam Clarke, and other rabbis of distinction
with me. The whole case, taken complexly, indicates that death for murder was
the penalty affixed by the justice of the antediluvian world.
From this
fragment of antediluvian history, we shall turn to the /325/ more copious
details of the postdiluvian. It is worthy of special consideration that the
first act of legislation in the new world, while the whole human race was in
Noah's family, was AN ACT AGAINST MURDER. This was a law not for Jew or
Gentile--not for Egyptian, Chaldean, Greek or Roman--but, being enacted before
any of them existed, for the whole human race. It was not an act against any
particular kind of murder--such as parricide or fratricide--but an act against
murder simply on its own account. The occasions and circumstances accompanying
the enactment of many laws are explanatory of them. These are worthy of special
attention. The whole world, one household excepted, had been destroyed by the
immediate hand of God. This destruction was made necessary because of the
unparalleled violence that filled the earth. One family was wholly destroyed.
This family was that of Cain, to which all cases of murder, or of punishment
for it, named in the old world, belonged. The earth being thus depopulated, the
family of Cain and of Lamech being wholly destroyed--to prevent the increase of
crime and the necessity of a similar catastrophe, God gave to man, by a
positive and express precept, the power, the authority and the injunction to
cut off all murderers.
The
occasion of this act of legislation, and the positive and peremptory terms in
which it is expressed, alike commend it to our consideration and regard. It is
expressed in the following words:- - "AT THE HAND OF EVERY MAN'S BROTHER
WILL I REQUIRE THE LIFE OF MAN. WHOSO SHEDDETH MAN'S BLOOD, BY MAN SHALL HIS
BLOOD BE SHED: FOR IN THE IMAGE OF GOD MADE HE MAN." No statute was ever
more free from ambiguity, or more intelligible, than this one. I never have met
with one who misunderstood it. Why, then, is its Divine obligation not
universally felt and acknowledged? To one unacquainted with the power of
sympathy, especially when its victim is seized with a morbid philanthropy or
charmed with the fascinations of a new theory, it will appear somewhat
mysterious how a precept so express, so authoritative and peremptory could be
disposed of or evaded. It is done by the magic of a single assumption:--
"Christianity is more mild and generous and philanthropic than the law of
Moses." But that is a provision of the law of Moses, is an assumption
which rests on the simple ground that Moses the lawgiver wrote the book of
Genesis. One might as justly assume that Noah's ark or Melchizedek's
pontificate was a part of the law of Moses, because Moses is the only person
who wrote their history. Form the age of spiritual Quakerism until now, the
abolitionists of capital punishment /326/ generally occupy this ground. As
there is no dispute about the meaning of the precept, the only to dispose of it
is to locate it amongst the Jewish rites and usages which have been abolished.
but the simple fact that this precept was promulged in the year of the world
1658, and that Moses gave not the law till the year 2513--that is, full eight
hundred and fifty five years after--is a fact so prominent and so indisputable
as to render any other refutation of the assumption a work of the most
gratuitous supererogation. I wonder why the same romantic genius that embodied
with the Jewish code a precept given to the whole human family almost a
thousand years before there was a Jewish nation, did not also embody with the
same code, and appropriate to the same people, the right to eat animal food,
then for the first time given to man--the covenant of day and night, of summer
and winter, of seed-time and harvest, indicated and confirmed by the celestial
arch which God erected upon the bosom of a cloud in token of his "covenant
with all flesh." The constitution that guarantees the continuance of day
and night and the seasons of the year also secures and protects the life of man
from the violence of man, by a statute simultaneously promulged and committed
to the father of the new world for the benefit of the whole human race. Why not
also represent this, too, as done away, and thus place the world without the
precincts of the covenanted mercies given to Noah for his family and recorded
by Moses the man of God? there is not, then, the shadow of a reason for the
assumption that the present human family is not obliged to enforce the statute
above named. The right to eat animal food, to expect the uninterrupted
succession of seasons, and the obligation to put the murderer to death, are of
equal antiquity and of the same Divine authority. Every one claiming any
interest in the world, because of his relation to Noah, and God's charter of
privileges granted to him, must either show, by some authority equally express
and incontrovertible, that God has abolished one part of it and perpetuated the
remainder, or advocate capital punishment upon Divine authority.
But still
more convincing and decisive is the reason assigned by the divine Author of the
statute commanding capital punishment. It is in these words:-- "FOR IN THE
IMAGE OF GOD MADE HE MAN." A reason, indeed, for the statute, worthy of
God to propound and worthy of man to honor and regard. Why a reason so forcible
and so full of eloquence and authority could be so frequently disparaged by an
intelligent and Christian community, is, to my mind, indicative not merely of
the want of piety, but of that of humanity and self--respect. The reason here
assigned for this precept places the crime of murder in an entirely new /327/
attitude before the mind. Much, indeed has ben said of this crime--of its
enormous dimensions--of its moral turpitude--its appalling guilt--its
diabolical malignity; but here it is presented to us as the greatest insult
which man can offer to his Creator--to the Supreme Majesty of the universe,
apart from all its bearings upon human society and its unfortunate victim. On
one occasion the Messiah said of Satan that he "was a liar and a murderer
from the beginning." It is impossible, then that we can exaggerate the
wickedness and malignancy of murder. No one has yet been able to do it justice.
It desecrates in effigy, and, as far as the impotent arm of flesh gas power,
destroys, the once brightest image of the invisible and eternal God that adorns
any province of his vast and glorious universe. Man is still great in his
ruins. Once the most exact and beautiful and impotent similitude of the Great
Original of universal being, he is to be reverenced; and, when renewed in the
moral image of his Maker, he is to be loved and admired not only as the noblest
work of almighty power, but as the special and exclusive object of redeeming
grace and mercy. But it is enough for our present purpose to know that it
making it the duty of society to avenge this crime, God makes its dishonor to
his own image the paramount reason why the life of the murderer should be taken
from him. The Most High does not give many reasons for his precepts; but, when
he gives one, it is worthy of himself and of the occasion, and claims the
profound respect of every discerning and moral man.
Before we
dismiss this divine statute, which has never been repealed, which never can be
abolished, we must add one other remark, in the form of an argument against the
possibility of abrogation. the reason given for slaying the murderer is one of
perpetual validity. If it was ever good and obligatory, it must always be so.
So long as it stands true that man was created in the image of God, so long it
will bind every religious and moral people to take away the life of a murderer.
It is, therefore, of immutable and perpetual obligation.
We shall
now briefly glance at the criminal code of the Jewish nation. merely to see whether
it harmonizes with the prominent statutes of the postdiluvian, if not of the
antediluvian, age. It is often very properly observed that the Jewish nation
was placed under a theocracy. Punishment by death was, under it, somewhat
extended beyond the single crime of murder. Various crimes affecting human
life, endangering or implying murder, were, under the special government of
God, amongst a people whose ecclesiastic and political consti-- /328/ tutions
were one and the same, punishable by death. According to the latest and one of
the most respectable treatises yet written on the "Elements of moral
Science" by one of the living ornaments of Trinity Collage, Cambridge, the
Jewish code took a proper view of polity. For, as Mr. Whewell very profoundly
observes, "It is to be recollected that one requisite for our advancing
towards a state of society is generally satisfactory, is the establishment of
moral rules as realities; and to this, at present, THERE APPEARS TO BE NO WAY
EXCEPT BY MAKING IGNOMINIOUS DEATH THE CLIMAX OF SCALE OF PUNISHMENTS." It
is, indeed the climax of several categories in the Jewish code. Not only that
he mortally smote a fellow-citizen, but he that smote his father or his mother,
whether mortally or not; he that stole a man and sold him; he that cursed his
parents; the reckless owner of an animal that killed, when through his neglect
life was lost; all that practised witchcraft, blasphemy, incest, sodomy,
bestiality, &c. were deemed worthy of death. Both the letter and the spirit
of the Jewish code on the matter of murder, and the reasons given for exacting
life for life, demand our special attention: we shall therefore copy a few of
the more prominent statutes of that institution.
In use: execution of Mary Surratt, Lewis Powell,
David Herold, and George Atzerodt, convicted of conspiracy in
the assassination
of Abraham Lincoln, on a gallows constructed for the occasion
|
The
fullest summary of the ordinances concerning manslaughter and murder, enjoined
upon the jews, is found in the book of Numbers, with some of the reasons
annexed, indicative of the philosophy of the Divine requisitions. We shall read
the whole passage:--
9. And
the Lord spake unto Moses, saying,
10. Speak
unto the children of Israel, and say unto them, When ye be come over Jordan
into the land of Cannan,
11. Then
ye shall appoint ye cities to be cities of refuge for you; that the slayer may
flee thither which killeth any person at unawares.
12. And
they shall be unto you cities for refuge from the avenger, that the man slayer
die not until he stand before the congregation in judgement.
13. And
of these cities which ye shall give, six cities have ye for refuge.
14. Ye
shall give three cities on this side Jordan, and three cities shall ye give in
the land of Canaan, which shall be cities of refuge.
15. These
six cities shall be refuge both for the children of Israel, and for the
stranger, and for the sojourner among them; that everyone who killeth any person
unawares may flee thither.
16. And
if he smite him with an instrument of iron so that he die, he is a murderer:
the murderer shall surely be put to death. /329/
17. And
if he smite him with a throwing stone, wherewith he may die, and if he die, he is
a murderer: the murderer shall surely be put to death.
18. Or if
he smite him with a hand--weapon of wood, wherewith he may die, and if he die,
he is a murderer: the murderer shall surely be put to death.
19. The
revenger of blood himself shall slay the murderer: when he meeteth him he shall
slay him.
20. But
if he thrust him of hatred, or hurl at him by laying of wait, that he die;
21. Or in
enmity smite him with his hand, that he die; he that smote him shall surely be
put to death; for he is a murderer: the revenger of blood shall slay the
murderer when he meeteth him.
22. But if he thrust him suddenly, without
enmity, or have cast upon him anything without laying of wait,
23. Or
with any stone, wherewith a man may die, seeing him not, and cast it upon him,
that he die, and was not his enemy, neither sought his harm;
24. Then
the congregation shall judge between the slayer and the revenger of blood,
according to these judgements:
25. And
the congregation shall deliver the slayer out of the hand of revenger of blood,
and the congregation shall restore him to the city of his refuge, whither he
was fled.
26. But
if the slayer shall at any time come without the borders of the city of his
refuge, wither he was fled;
27. And
the revenger of blood find him without the borders of the city of his refuge,
and the revenger of blood kill the slayer; he shall not be guilty of blood;
28.
Because he should have remained in the city of his refuge until the death of
the high-priest; but after the death of the high-priest the slayer shall return
to the land of his possession.
29. So
these things shall be for a statute of judgement unto you, throughout your
generations, in all your dwellings.
30. Whoso
killeth any person, the murderer shall be put to death by the mouth of
witnesses; but one witness will not testify against any person to cause him to
die.
31.
Moreover, ye shall take no satisfaction for the life of a murderer which is
guilty of death; but he shall be surely put to death.
32. And
ye shall take no satisfaction for him that is fled to the city of his refuge,
that he should come again to dwell in the land, until the death of the
high-priest.
33. So ye
shall not pollute the land wherein ye are; for blood it defileth the land: and
the land can not be cleansed of the blood that is shed therein, but by the
blood of him that shed it. (Num. ch.xxxv.)
The
ordinance for erecting the cities of refuge under which they were placed, like
every other part of the mosaic institu- /330/ tion, commend the wisdom justice,
benevolence of the lawgiver and King of Israel. Two great objects were
contemplated and secured by that institution--a refuge for the innocent, and a
CAVEAT against manslaughter.
When
anyone killed another by mere accident, without any malice or evil intent on
the part of him that did it, he was, when admitted into anyone of these cities,
legally secure against the avenger of blood. The right of avenging blood, from
Adam to Moses, during the whole patriarchal age, seems to have been, with
Divine approbation, conferred upon the nearest kinsman of the deceased. It is
very evident, not merely from the silence of the law, but from the retention of
the ancient official name that the creation of these cities created no officer
in the land other than he to whom, from the beginning, the duty had belonged.
The next in blood still retained the right to avenge his murdered relative.
These cities were, therefore, intended to protect the innocent from rash and
unjust executions. Before that time, the alter, it appears, (Ex. xxi. 14,) had
been the sanctuary of refuge for the unfortunate manslayer.
But, in
the second place, the cities of refuge were not unlike penitentiaries, to which
even an innocent manslayer was required, at the peril of his life, to be
confined until the death of that high-priest under whose administration the
event had taken place. This sometimes happens to be for life. If at any time
during the pontificate of the high-priest he presumed to go out of the city ,
it was at the hazard of his life. This was placing a new guard around human
life. A wise provision, truly, against manslaughter! He that was so unfortunate
as to kill any person by the veriest accident, incurred two imminent
risks--that of being killed, before he got into the city of refuge, by the
avenger of blood; and, if not killed, that of being confined for years--perhaps
all his life -- within its walls, away from his family and home.
But in
the case of murder, whether premeditated or from the rage of passion, the
cities of refuge afforded no asylum whatever. On trial and conviction the
criminal was, in all cases, taken from them and put to death. For the guilty
murderer thee was no asylum. If escaped the hand of the avenger of blood while
fleeing to the city , if, perchance, he fled there for trial, he always
expiated the blood that he had shed by his own.
It is
scarcely necessary to remark how often and with what clearness and authority it
promulged--"The murderer shall surely be put to death;" and again,
"The avenger of blood himself shall kill him when he meeteth him." No
one will, I presume, after a single reading /331/ of this statute, require any
other evidence that capital punishment was divinely ordained during the whole
period of Old Testament history--that it was an essential part of the Jewish
institution, and during its continuance extended much beyond the patriarchal
requisition.
But there
is a reason connected with these ordinances that demands our special
consideration. Like that given to Noah, it has no respect to time, place or
circumstance. It belongs exclusively to no age, to no nation or people. It is a
reason, too, why murder shall not be pardoned, and why the Lord so solemnly and
so positively said, "You shall take no satisfaction for the life of a
murderer"--he must not be ransomed at any price. Does anyone ask why there
should be no ransom, no commutation, no pardon? The answer, the reason, is one
of fearful import. It is this:--"THE LAND CAN NOT BE CLEANSED OF THE BLOOD
THAT IS SHED THEREIN BUT BY THE BLOOD OF HIM THAT SHED IT." So God
almighty has ordained in his infinite wisdom , justice and benevolence. It is
enough. HE has said it. No tears of repentance, no contrition of heart, no
agony of soul, can expiate the sin of murder. As soon could the breath of a
mortal melt the polar mountains of ice, dissolve the Siberian snows and fill
the dreary wastes with verdure, the beauty and fragrance of ancient Eden, as
soon would the sigh of remorse quicken into life the ashes of the murdered
dead, or a single penetentail tear extinguish the fires of hell, as any
expiation or ablution of mortal hand, other than the blood of the murderer,
atone to God's violated law, do honor to his insulted Majesty and purify the
land from the dark defilement of unavenged blood.
I cannot
but tremble for our country, if this be the decision of the Governor of
nations, when I reflect upon the multitude that have in single combat
sacrificed each other, in purpose or in fact, at the shrine of a false and
factitos honor; and upon those who, in the sullen rage and malice of the
dastardly assassin, avenged their imaginary wrongs by the blood of their
fellow-citizens; and upon those who sought to conceal their infamous crimes of
lust and passion--of burglary, arson and rapine--with the blood of those who
might have been witnesses against them; I say, when I reflect upon the hundreds
and the thousands thus murdered, whose blood yet unexpiated still pollutes our
soil, and through the vagueness and ambiguity of our laws, the venality,
corruption or incompetency of our tribun, or the servility or self- /332/
willedness of our chief magistrates, yet cries to heaven for vengeance, not
merely upon the head of those that shed it, but upon the government and the
people that still suffer them to live, methinks I see a most portentous cloud,
dark, swollen and lowering surcharged with the fires of divine indignation,
ready to burst in accumulated vengeance upon our blood polluted-land.
But, in
extenuation of our apathy or as an apology for our indifference, it is sometimes
assumed that the Messiah has forever abolished the bloody code of Moses and the
patriarchs, and has preached a larger benevolence and forgiveness to nations.
What a baseless assumption! What an outrage upon the character of the Messiah!
True, indeed, he came not to judge the world, to act the civil magistrate, the
civil lawgiver, or to assume regal authority over any nation or people of this
world. His kingdom was spiritual and heavenly. In it, he would not have an eye
for an eye, a tooth for a tooth, or stripe for stripe. He would not have his
followers go to law for any violence, fraud or wrong inflicted on them on his
account. They might, indeed, sue those out of his kingdom for civil wrongs in
civil courts, or they might consent to be sued for unjust demands upon them in
their political and civil relations; but any wrong, violence or compulsion
inflicted on them for their religion, their conscientious allegiance to him,
they were to endure cheerfully, and rejoice that they were counted worthy to suffer
wrong, or even shame for his name's sake. But he that hence argues for the
abolition of civil government, of civil penalties, or for the abrogation of the
statutes given to mankind by God himself, founded on his own perfections and
the immutable relations of things, not merely typical and adumbrative in their
nature, but jurisprudential and for the safety of society, shocks all common
sense. As well might we say that morality and the moral character of God are
mutable things. It enacts no civil statutes. It does not even designate the
persons between whom the institutions of marriage may be consummated. It
abrogates nothing in the Old Testament that was not substantiated in Christ, or
that was not peculiar to the twelve tribes. But we have shown that the precept
in discussion belonged, not to any institution, Patriarchal, Jewish or
Christian, but to the whole family of man.
Does not
an apostle say that "the law is good if a man use it lawfully"? Does
he not say that "the law was not made for a righteous man, but for the
lawless and disobedient: for murderers, man-slayers, /333/ man-stealers,
thieves, liars, perjured persons," &c.? And surely for all these
evil-doers it has, or ought to have its penalties. In executing these eon their
proper subjects the law is used lawfully.
Again,
does not Paul teach that the "powers that be are ordained of
God"?--that the magistrate "is his minister," and that he
rightfully wears a sword not his own, but God's? And, in the name of reason,
why have a sword in the state, and worn by the civil magistrate, if it be
unlawful or unchristian to put anyone to death on any account whatever? That
would, indeed, be to "bear the sword in vain;" a thing which the
apostles themselves would have reprobated. Christians, then, must remember that
the magistrate is God's armed minister, and that he must be obeyed by every
Christian man, not merely through the fear of his wrath , or of his avenging
sword, but for the sake of a conscientious regard to God's authority, whose
minister of justice he is. The civil magistrate is now the civil avenger of
blood. Paul calls him "A MESSENGER OF WRATH upon him that doeth
evil."
There is
not, then, a word in the Old Testament or the new inhibiting capital
punishment, nor a single intimation that it should be abolished. On the
contrary, reasons are given as the basis of the requisition of life for life,
which never can be set aside--which are as forcible at this hour as they were
in the days of Cain, Noah, Moses and Jesus Christ. We reiterate the statute
with clearer conviction of its obligation and utility on every consideration of
the broad, deep, solid and enduring premises on which it is
founded:--"Thou shalt take (no ransom) no satisfaction for the life of the
murderer."--"He that sheddeth man's blood, by man shall his blood be
shed; for in the image of God made he man."- -"The land can not be
cleaned from blood but by the blood of him that shed it." For this purpose
the magistrate is "God's minister, and avenger, to execute wrath upon him
that doeth evil."
The
necessity, utility and importance of capital punishment, we must regard, on the
premises already considered, as unequivocally and irrefragably established, so
far as divine authority can require or establish any thing. And although the
most plain and striking passages, found in patriarchal, Jewish and Christian
institutions, have been adduced and partially considered, the half has not been
told, nor the argument fully developed. A single address on such an occasion as
the present is not sufficient for a subject so comprehensive and important. It
would, indeed, require a volume rather than one short lecture. Conscious of our
inability fully to discuss such a question /334/ on such an occasion, we shall
therefore add but a few remarks further.
It has
been said, not by those of old time, but by those of our time, that the sixth
precept of the Decalogue, "THOU SHALT NOT KILL," inhibits all taking
away of human life. A sect of extreme pietists on Long Island, it is reported,
gave to the precept a broader interpretation, and forbade the killing of any
living creature for food. they are as consistent as one who says the precept
"THOU SHALT NOT KILL" prohibits capital punishment. It is also the
precept that calls for the blood of him that violates it.
Moses did
not himself so interpret this precept; for on the very day that he descended
from the mount with the autograph in his hand, he commanded the sons of Levi to
gird on their swords and kill the idolaters who had eaten and drank and danced
to an idol-- of whom no less than three thousand fell that day.
I
introduce this case for another purpose--to repudiate an objection urged
against capital punishment. It is asked, What Christian man, or what man of
delicate moral sensibility, could execute such a sentence--could dispatch to
the judgement-seat a criminal crimsoned with the blood of his fellow-man?
It is not
the sheriff's hand--it is not the sword of the executioner. It is the hand of
God--it is the sword of justice that takes away that life that which he himself
gave, because the criminal has murderously taken away a life which he could not
give.
Is the
hand of man purer than the hand of an angel? And who was it that, in one
memorable night, passing through the land of Egypt, by a single stroke smote to
death the first-born of all the realms of Pharaoh, from the royal palace down
to the cottage of the meanest serf that breathed upon his soil! And who was it
that, on another fatal night, while passing through the camp of the insolent
Assyrian chief, killed one hundred and eighty-five thousand of his most valiant
men? WAS IT NOT THE ANGEL OF THE LORD? Nay, rather, who was it that in the days
of Noah inflicted with his own hand capital and condign punishment upon a world
filled with violence and with blood? Who was it that rained down fire and
brimstone from the heavens on the devoted cities of the Plain, saving, as in
the former case, but a single family? was it not the Lord himself in person?
And what
shall we say of the father of the faithful, returning from the slaughter of the
confederate kings?--of Moses, as the messenger of God, slaying not merely a
single Egyptian, but smiting with his rod, in the depths of the Red Sea, the
strength, the pride and the glory of /335/ Egypt?--of Joshua, the son of Nun,
destroying seven idolatrous nations?--of Samuel, hewing to pieces with his own
hand the king of Amalek?--of David and his hundred battles? time would fail me
to name all the instances in which God has made the purest, the holiest and the
best of men, as well as angels, the executioners of his justice. I shall
mention another case--the case of Joab--one that, before I understood the
statutes of the Lord on the subject of murder, often perplexed me. There lay
king David, the beloved of his God, on the bed of death; and while making his
last will and testament, he remembered Joab--the brave, the valorous, the
mighty Joab--than whom no king could boast of a truer friend or a greater or
more successful general--his own kinsman, too--his own sister's son. He names
him to his son Solomon, his successor of the sceptre of Israel. And what is his
will concerning Joab? What honors or rewards has he in store for him? Hearken
to his words:--"Solomon, my son--thou knowest also what Joab, the son of
Zeruiah, did to me, and what he did to the two captains of the hosts of Israel:
to Abner, the son of Ner, and to Amasa, the son of Jether, whom he slew and
shed the blood of war in peace, and put the blood of war upon his girdle that
was about his loins, and in the shoes that were upon his feet. Do, therefore
according to thy wisdom, and let not his hory head go down to the grave in
peace." So willed the dying David. And what did Solomon his son? There was
no city of refuge for Joab, but flying into the tabernacle and taking hold of
the horns of the alter, Joab said, "Here I will die." And what said
the king? "Go, Benaiah, do as he hath said. fall upon him and bury him,
that," adds the king, "thou myest take away the innocent blood that
is shed therein, but by the blood of him that shed it."
But we
have yet a stronger case--the case of David's son and David's Lord. His words
are oracles from which there is no appeal; his example is an argument to which
there is no response. Is he, or is he not, on the side of capital punishment?
While on earth he was a SAVIOUR. In heaven he is now a KING. Hereafter he will
appear in the character of a JUDGE and an avenger. we ask not what he will do
then in finally and eternally punishing the impenitent. We ask not what he did
while on earth as a Saviour; for then "he came to save men's lives, and
not to destroy." But we ask, What did he do when he became king, when
exalted to be the prince and the governor /336/ of the universe? He intimated
the leading principles of his government before he was crowned Lord of all, to
those Jews who were intent on his destruction. "I will," said he,
"send you prophets, wise men and scribes. Some of them you will kill ad
crucify, others you will scourge in your synagogues and persecute from city to
city, that upon you may come all the righteous blood shed upon earth, from the
blood of Abel to the blood of Barachias, whom ye slew between the temple and
the alter. Verily, I say to you, all these things shall come on this
generation." Did he when king execute this threat? Ask Josephus, Taccitus
and a hundred other witnesses. as governor of the world, he dispatched Titus
with a Roman army, and laid siege to Jerusalem and other cities in Judea. In
the whole of these various wars and sieges--in the destruction of the city and
the temple, he killed more than one million of the rebellious Jews, and sent
the remainder into exile. But this is not the only case. It is but the first
one of notoriety in his reign of justice. Ever since he ascended the throne his
promise is, "All that take the sword shall perish with the sword." As
king of nations and governor of the world, he executes wrath by his
"ministers of justice" upon wicked men and nations, in the temporal
punishments which he awards. According to king David, in the second psalm, when
the messiah should be placed as king on Mount Zion, he was to "rule the
nations with a rod of iron, and to break them in pieces like a potter's
vessel." this he has already done in more than one instance, and will yet
do in many more. But he does it not in person, but by his"
ministers." Still, he does it.
It being
evident, as we suppose, that capital punishment is not only countenanced by
innumerable Biblical precedents, but that it is also most positively enjoined
upon all persons to whom God has revealed his will, who are intrusted with the
government of the world, we shall henceforth regard it as a divine precept and
requisition, to which we are bound to yield our cordial assent; not because it
chances to fall in with our theories of what is expedient, useful or consonant
to the genius of our age and government, but because of the supreme authority
that enacts it-- because it is a decree of the King of the universe, the
ultimate Judge of the living and the dead, and because he himself has practised
it, and still continues to practise it, as moral governor of the world.
Though
not disposed to appear paradoxical, I hesitate not to avow the conviction that
the divine ordinance is as merciful as it is just--that, for example, it was
most humane and merciful on the part of David to command his son Solomon to
take away the life of Joab. I cite this /337/ case and avow this conviction,
for the sake of those opposers of capital punishment, who, under the pretence
of a more refined and enlarged philanthropy, are, nowadays, declaiming both
eloquently and impassionedly against capital punishment because of its alleged
cruelty and inhumanity. That those who thus inveigh against it are
philanthropic in purpose and feeling, I doubt not. But that they are so in
fact, is not quite so evident.
In
seeking to abolish capital punishment, do they not divest human life of one of
its main pillars of defence? In all countries, and, I believe, an all ages,
murders increase and diminish in the ratio of the certainty of the exaction of
life for life. It must, in the nature of things, be so, Everything is safe or
unsafe as it is guarded or not guarded by education--by law--by the magnitude
and certainty or uncertainty of rewards and punishments. In abolishing capital
punishment, the main bulwark against the perpetration of murder falls to the
ground. The broad shield of a nation's safety and defence from violence and
blood is broken to pieces, and the honorable and virtuous citizen, naked and
defenceless, left exposed to the murderous assaults of malice and envy. Of what
avail is the bare possibility of a punishment infinitely less than the injury
inflicted on the individual and the state,--enfeebled, too, as it must be, by a
hundred chances of escape against one of apprehension and conviction? Who could
feel himself safe under a government where there is no protection of his life
against the furious passions which not unfrequently display themselves in the
most appalling forms, in some of those terrific monsters with which human
society more or less abounds? exile, confinement in prison or workhouses, are
to such demons as an act of Congress to a South American tiger, or as the
stubble to Job's Leviathan.
[PHOTO SOURCE: http:// |
In saving
a murderer from death through a morbid compassion, society acts with more
indiscretion than the fabled husbandman who, in commiseration, carried home to
his hearth a congealed serpent, which, when warmed to life, fatally struck the
children of its benefactor. In saving from the penalty of God's law a single
murderer, society sins against itself, as well as against God, and occasions,
or may occasion, the destruction of one or more of its citizens. If everyone
convicted of murder in any of its various forms was infallibly put to death,
can any intelligent citizen imagine that crimes of this sort would not rather
diminish than increase? The strong probability of escape disarms every legal
punishment of its terror to evil-doers. /338/
It has
been observed that murder and robbery more frequently accompany each other in
all states that punish the robber as well as that murderer by death, than it
those that never visit theft or highway-robbery with capital punishment. As
true as it is that in those states where murder is seldom punished with death,
the crime, so far as my readings and observations go, is more frequently
perpetrated than in those states in which its proper punishment is much more
certain. We cannot, therefore, but think that the court of Judge Lynch would
not have held its sessions so frequently in late years, had it not been that
other courts so often failed to hold their sessions, with that certainty of
capital punishment for capital offenses which right reason, human prudence and
God's holy law so clearly and authoritatively demand. We cannot but trace the
present appalling increase of murders in our country to those morbid
philanthropists who, in the form of judges, juries and chief magistrates, in
these days of new theories, experiments, and irreverence for God's law and
authority, are ever and anon making void our laws, lame though they be, by
suffering the convicted murderer to live.
The
master-spirits of France, now, and at former times, have been much addicted to
theorize against capital punishment. Robespierre in early life published a
treatise against capital punishment, but when he rose to power, he became the
presiding genius of the guillotine. Strange that such a theory should have been
popular in France before the terror began! France, however, is not the only
country that has theorized against the Bible and its justice. Nor is it the
only one that suffers from it . Indeed, all states that have more or less
theorized against capital punishment have been signally punished by and
increase of the crime. In truth, it is as some poet says--
"Mercy
murders in pardoning him that kills."
The
protection and safety of human life is the first and paramount concern of every
intelligent and moral community on earth. The first statute ever enacted by the
heavenly father in the present world , as before observed, was a statute FOR
PRESERVING LIFE. I am not singular, I hope, in judging of the civilization of
every community by the care it takes of human life. May not the religious and
moral character of a community be fairly estimated by the value it puts upon human
life, and the care it takes of it, as indicated in its statute-books, its
courts of justice, its general police, and its numerous and various means of
defense against the accidents and dangers which may imperil it? And may not
these be learned from its public highways, its public /339/ conveyances, its
public buildings, and from the character and capacities of the officers to
whose fidelity these great interests are committed, as well as from the various
exactions of service, and the extent of the penalties inflicted upon them for
delinquency or malfeasance in the discharge of their duties?
In
countries long settled, do we see the public highways bordered with dead trees,
whose ponderous and decaying branches are bending over our heads? Are the
streams that cross them unbridged, or, if bridged, are these bridges, decayed
and dilapidating under the wasting hand of time, permitted to betray the unwary
traveller into danger? Are their dread precipices unwalled, their deep ravines
uncovered, their miry sloughs unpaved? Are their public conveyances by land and
sea, by lake and river, uncomfortable or unsafe, as far as science or art can
promote, either safety or comfort? if so, must we not regard such a people as
imperfectly education--as but partially civilized--as essentially defective in
the pure and excellent morality of the Christian religion?
If the
Lawgiver of the universe, when acting as king of Israel, found that man guilty
of blood of the roof of whose house there was no defense of falling over , when
it became necessary to walk upon it--if he had said to every subject of his
kingdom, "When thou buildest a house, then shalt thou make a battlement
for thy roof, that thou bring not blood upon thy house should any man fall from
thence,"--and if he held every man liable for the damage accruing from a
pit which he had digged and left uncovered, what would we think of those
Christian Philanthropists that pay so little regard to the life of man as not
only to subject him to all the dangers of bad roads, bad bridges, bad coached,
bad boats and bad officers, but, when his life is taken by the hand of a
duellist or an assassin, extenuate the offence, and abolish the proper
punishment, and allow this wretch again to go at large and hazard other deed of
violence and blood?
In
conclusion, we would only ask, who can form a just estimate of the value of the
life of one man, either to himself or to society? No one lives or dies to
himself alone. The unhappy victim of a murderer's fear or hate has not only
lost his life, but the world has lost it too. And what is life? Ay, what is
life, to its possessor, to his relatives, to his country and to the world? How
much would he himself take for it? Ask not the princes and the nobles of the
earth in the morning of life--in the enjoyment of all the honors, pleasures and
possessions of earth that imagination can body forth, or passions can desire.
Ask not the men of genius, who dwell in enchanted palaces, who drink /340/ the
pleasures of imagination from the purest and loftiest fountains of creation.
Ask not poets, orators and philosophers, who find a heaven in the admiration of
their contemporaries, and an eternal award in the worship and envy of
posterity. Ask not the military chieftain, returning form the field of blood,
flushed with the victories he has won, and crowned wit the laurels of a hundred
battles. But ask that poor, old, decrepit gally-slave, who has seen his
fourscore years, what posthumous fame he would accept, what sum of money would
satisfy him, for the pittance of days that might yet be alloted to him. One's
life might be safely staked on it, that neither the wealth of a Croesus nor the
fame of a Napolean would be accepted by him for his chances of another year.
Again,
what immense stakes, has society in the lives of some men! What great interests
are often wrapped up in the life of a single individual! It is not the interest
of one city, one state, or one empire; it is not the interest of one age or of
one generation of men; but the interests of a world, and of ages to come, that
sometimes providentially hang upon the life of a single individual. Let any one
conversant with the history of the last three or four centuries consider how
much interest had the world in a few individuals--in such men as Christopher Columbus,
Martin Luther, Sir Francis Bacon, Sir Isaac Newton, Benjamin Franklin, Robert
Fulton, and George Washington. Suppose that each of these had met with some
Aaron Burr, as did Alexander Hamilton, (a name of no inferior fame--whose
death, as a national misfortune, no living man can estimate) what would have
been the present condition of the world? Can any man form a proper estimate?
Can any one subtract from science, and art, and society, the exact amount of
our indebtedness to any one of them, much less to them all? It is from such a
sacrifice as this, laid upon the altar of the implacable demon of a false
honor, immolated at the promptings of malice of envy, that we learn the demerit
of the murderer--what the world may lose by permitting him to live, and why the
fiercest thunderbolts of Almighty wrath are treasured up for him.
From this
view of the subject, (and who that venerates the authority of the Bible can
reasonably dissent from it?) may we not entreat every patriot, philanthropist
and Christian in our country to use his best endeavors to create a sound public
opinion on the obligations resting on every State government to exterminate the
crime of murder by a firm, persevering and uniform execution of the murderer
according to the Divine precept? Every one can aid in this cause, more or less.
/341/ And now is a most important crisis. While so many are for taking away the
greatest restraint and for substituting a less one, under the preposterous
assumption that man is wiser than God, and that a minor punishment will be more
effectual than a greater one, it is high time that the real friends of man
should speak out.
And
should I not more especially address myself to the softer, more sensitive and
humane portion of my audience--to that sex to whose soul-subduing counsels and
fostering hands the God of nature and of society has so wisely and kindly
assigned the formation of human character, and to whose influence, direct and
indirect, he has almost entirely consigned the destiny of man under the most endearing
and fascinating of all titles and associations--those of MOTHER, WIFE and
SISTER?
If the
ladies in this our age of civilization will only concur with us in opinion, and
lend their mighty aid in propagating right views on this subject--if they will
combine their irresistible energies in this cause of genuine humanity, and
frown from their presence not only the reckless duellist, but every one who
pleads his cause or countenances in any way his factitious code of ignoble
honor--if they will forever discard from their admiration and esteem every
candidate for their favor who is known to wear upon his person any weapon
whatever, fabricated with a view to violence against the life of man--the might
work is done. Then may be averted the vials of Divine indignation which must be
poured out on every government and country deaf to the demands of God's
righteous law and regardless of the true safety and happiness of society.
I can
only add my earnest prayer that a timely repentance may dissipate that dark and
portentous cloud that yet lowers over our beloved country; that by a just
consideration of the dignity of man as created in the image of God, the value
of human life as respects the eternal citizens, the solemn requisitions of the
divine law, exacting in all cases the life of the murderer--those having it in
their power to form, direct and govern society may perceive that it is alike an
oracle of reason, of justice and of mercy that "whosoever sheddeth man's
blood, by man shall his blood be shed," and that, therefore, no ransom or
substitute shall be taken for the life of the murderer, inasmuch as, by the
eternal and immutable law of God, "the land cannot be cleansed of the
blood that is shed therein but by the blood of him that shed it."
No comments:
Post a Comment